Asian Massive Crew Community 2002/2020 - View Single Post - Moral relativism or ethical relativism
View Single Post

Metaethical Moral Relativism
Old 15-10-2011   #2
Karmadev
Wild Poster
 
Karmadev's Avatar
 
Karmadev is offline
Join Date: Jul 2005
Posts: 2,543
Male
Karmadev is on a distinguished road
My Mood:
CountryKarmadev's Flag is: United States
Post Thanks / Like
Thanks (Given):
Thanks (Received):
Likes (Given):
Likes (Received):
Dislikes (Given):
Dislikes (Received):

Star Sign: Star Sign
Status:
has no status.
Metaethical Moral Relativism

6. Metaethical Moral Relativism

Even if it were established that there are deep and widespread moral disagreements that cannot be rationally resolved, and that these disagreements are more significant than whatever agreements there may be, it would not immediately follow that MMR is correct. Other nonobjectivist conclusions might be drawn. In particular, opponents of objectivism might argue for moral skepticism, that we cannot know moral truths, or for a view that moral judgments lack truth-value (understood to imply a rejection of relative truth-value). Hence, proponents of MMR face two very different groups of critics: assorted kinds of moral objectivists and various sorts of moral nonobjectivists. The defender of MMR needs to establish that MMR is superior to all these positions, and this would require a comparative assessment of their respective advantages and disadvantages. It is beyond the scope of this article to consider the alternative positions (see the entries on moral cognitivism vs. non-cognitivism, moral anti-realism, moral epistemology, moral realism, and moral skepticism). What can be considered are the challenges the proponent of MMR faces and what may be said in response to them.

It might be thought that MMR, with respect to truth-value, would have the result that a moral judgment such as “suicide is morally right” could be both true and false—true when valid for one group and false when invalid for another. But this appears to be an untenable position: most people would grant that nothing can be both true and false. Of course, some persons could be justified in affirming S and other persons justified in denying it, since the two groups could have different evidence. But it is another matter to say S is both true and false.

A standard relativist response is to say that moral truth is relative in some sense. On this view, S is not true or false absolutely speaking, but it may be true-relative-to-X and false-relative-to-Y (where X and Y refer to the moral codes of different societies). This means that suicide is right for persons in a society governed by X, but it is not right for persons in a society governed by Y; and, the relativist may contend, there is no inconsistency in this conjunction properly understood.

It might be objected that the notion of relative truth fails to capture the sense in which ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ are normative terms about what ought to be as opposed to what is the case. The statement “suicide is morally right” is normative in this sense, but the statement “suicide is morally right for persons in a society governed by moral code X” is not normative, but descriptive: it tells us what persons who accept moral code X think, and as such it is something everyone could agree with, irrespective of their own moral code, if in fact this is what moral code X says (see Boghossian 2011a and 2011b). In response, it might be said that there are expressions of relativist moral statements that are normative. For instance, “suicide is morally right for us,” spoken by and to members of the group referred to by ‘us’, is not merely a description of what they believe: it tells them what they are morally permitted to do (in this sense, it is action-guiding).

Such relativist formulations may also give rise to a related and very common objection. Relativism often presents itself as an interpretation of moral disagreements: It is said to be the best explanation of rationally irresolvable or faultless moral disagreements. However, once moral truth is regarded as relative, the disagreements seem to disappear. For example, someone accepting X who affirms S is saying suicide is right for persons accepting X, while someone accepting Y who denies S is saying suicide is not right for persons accepting Y. It might well be that they are both correct and hence that they are not disagreeing with one another (rather as two people in different places might both be correct when one says the sun is shining and the other says it is not, or as two people in different countries may both be correct when one says something is illegal and the other says it is not). The relativist explanation dissolves the disagreement. But, then, why did it appear as a disagreement in the first place? An objectivist might say this is because people thinking this assume that moral truth is absolute rather than relative. If this were correct, the relativist could not maintain that MMR captures what people already believe. The contention would have to be that they should believe it, and the argument for relativism would have to be formulated in those terms. For example, the relativist might contend that MMR is the most plausible position to adopt insofar as moral judgments often give practically conflicting directives and neither judgment can be shown to be rationally superior to the other.

Another common objection, though probably more so outside philosophy than within it, is that MMR cannot account for the fact that some practices such as the holocaust in Germany or slavery in the United States are obviously objectively wrong. This point is usually expressed in a tone of outrage, often with the suggestion that relativists pose a threat to civilized society (or something of this sort). Proponents of MMR might respond that this simply begs the question, and in one sense they are right. However, this objection might reflect a more sophisticated epistemology, for example, that we have more reason to accept these objectivist intuitions than we have to accept any argument put forward in favor of MMR. This would bring us back to the arguments of the last section. Another relativist response would be to say that the practices in question, though widely accepted, were wrong according to the fundamental standards of the societies (for example, there were arguments against slavery presented in the United States prior to the Civil War). This would not show that the practices are objectively wrong, but it might mitigate the force of the critique. However, though this response may be plausible in some cases, it is not obvious that it always would be convincing.

This last response brings out the fact that a proponent of MMR needs a clear specification of that to which truth is relative. For example, if S is true-relative-to the moral code of a society, does this mean it is true-relative-to what people in the society think the moral code says or to what the fundamental standards of the moral code actually imply? These might not be the same. It is often supposed that truths can be undiscovered or that people can make mistakes about them. As just noted, a moral relativist could make sense of this by supposing that it is the fundamental standards of a moral code that are authoritative for people in a society that accepts that code. Hence, what is morally true-relative-to the moral code of a society is whatever the fundamental standards of the code would actually warrant. By this criterion, there could be moral truths that are unknown to people in the society that accepts the code, or these people could be mistaken in thinking something is a moral truth.

A similar point arises from the fact that it is sometimes thought to be an advantage of MMR that it maintains a substantial notion of intersubjective truth or justification: It avoids the defects of moral objectivism, on the one hand, and of moral skepticism and theories that disregard moral truth-value altogether, on the other hand, because it maintains that moral judgments do not have truth in an absolute sense, but they do have truth relative to the moral code of a society (and similarly for justification). This is thought to be an advantage because, notwithstanding the supposed difficulties with moral objectivism, morality is widely regarded as “not merely subjective,” and MMR can capture this. However, this purported advantage raises an important question for relativism: Why suppose moral judgments have truth-value relative to a society as opposed to no truth-value at all? If the relativist claims that a set of fundamental standards is authoritative for persons in a society, it may be asked why they have this authority. This question may arise in quite practical ways. For example, suppose a dissident challenges some of the fundamental standards of his or her society. Is this person necessarily wrong?

Various answers may be given to these questions. For example, it may be said that the standards that are authoritative in a society are those that reasonable and well-informed members of the society would generally accept. This might seem to provide a basis for normative authority. However, if this approach were taken, it may be asked why that authority rests only on reasonable and well-informed members of the society. Why not a wider group? Why not all reasonable and well-informed persons?

A different response would be to say that the standards that are authoritative for a society are the ones persons have agreed to follow as a result of some negotiation or bargaining process (as seen above, Harman has argued that we should understand some moral judgments in these terms). Once again, this might seem to lend those standards some authority. Still, it may be asked whether they really have authority or perhaps whether they have the right kind. For example, suppose the agreement had been reached in circumstances in which a few members of society held great power over the others (in the real world, the most likely scenario). Those with less power might have been prudent to make the agreement, but it is not obvious that such an agreement would create genuine normative authority—a point the dissident challenging the standards might well make. Moreover, if all moral values are understood in this way, how do we explain the authority of the contention that people should follow a set of values because they agreed to do so? Must there be a prior agreement to do what we agree to do?

A related objection concerns the specification of the society to which moral justification or truth are said to be relative. People typically belong to many different groups defined by various criteria: culture, religion, political territory, ethnicity, race, gender, etc. Moreover, while it is sometimes claimed that the values of a group defined by one of these criteria have authority for members of the group, such claims are often challenged. The specification of the relevant group is itself a morally significant question, and there appears to be no objective map of the world that displays its division into social groups to which the truth or justification of moral judgments are relative. A proponent of MMR needs a plausible way of identifying the group of persons to which moral truth or justification are relative.

Moreover, not only do people typically belong to more than one group, as defined by the aforementioned criteria, the values that are authoritative in each group a person belongs to may not always be the same. If I belong to a religion and a nationality, and their values concerning abortion are diametrically opposed, then which value is correct for me? This raises the question whether there is a basis for resolving the conflict consistent with MMR (the two groups might have conflicting fundamental standards) and whether in this circumstance MMR would entail that there is a genuine moral dilemma (meaning that abortion is both right and wrong for me). This point is not necessarily an objection, but a defender of MMR would have to confront these issues and develop a convincing position concerning them.

The fact that social groups are defined by different criteria, and that persons commonly belong to more than one social group, might be taken as a reason to move from relativism to a form of subjectivism. That is, instead of saying that the truth or justification of moral judgments is relative to a group, we should say it is relative to each individual (as noted above, relativism is sometimes defined to include both positions). This revision might defuse the issues just discussed, but it would abandon the notion of intersubjectivity with respect to truth or justification—what for many proponents of MMR is a chief advantage of the position. Moreover, a proponent of this subjectivist account would need to explain in what sense, if any, moral values have normative authority for a person as opposed to simply being accepted. The fact that we sometimes think our moral values have been mistaken is often thought to imply that we believe they have some authority that does not consist in the mere fact that we accept them.

Another set of concerns arises from purported facts about similarities among and interactions across different societies vis-ā-vis morality. People in one society sometimes make moral judgments about people in another society on the basis of moral standards they take to be authoritative for both societies. In addition, conflicts between societies are sometimes resolved because one society changes its moral outlook and comes to share at least some of the moral values of the other society. More generally, sometimes people in one society think they learn from the moral values of another society: They come to believe that the moral values of another society are better in some respects than their own (previously accepted) values. The Mondrian image of a world divided into distinct societies, each with it own distinctive moral values, makes it difficult to account for these considerations. If this image is abandoned as unrealistic, and is replaced by one that acknowledges greater moral overlap and interaction among societies (recall the Pollock image), then the proponent of MMR needs to give a plausible account of these dynamics. This is related to the problem of authority raised earlier: These considerations suggest that people sometimes acknowledge moral authority that extends beyond their own society, and a relativist needs to show why this makes sense or why people are mistaken in this acknowledgement.

7. Mixed Positions: A Rapprochement between Relativists and Objectivists?
Discussions of moral relativism often assume (as mostly has been assumed here so far) that moral relativism is the correct account of all moral judgments or of none. But perhaps it is the correct account of some moral judgments but not others or, more vaguely, the best account of morality vis-ā-vis these issues would acknowledge both relativist and objectivist elements. Such a mixed position might be motivated by some of the philosophical questions already raised (recall also the suggestion in the section on experimental philosophy that some people may be “meta-ethical pluralists”). On the empirical level, it might be thought that there are many substantial moral disagreements but also some striking moral agreements across different societies. On the metaethical plane, it might be supposed that, though many disagreements are not likely to be rationally resolved, other disagreements may be (and perhaps that the cross-cultural agreements we find have a rational basis). The first point would lead to a weaker form of DMR The second point, the more important one, would imply a modified form of MMR (see the suggestions in the last paragraph of section 4). This approach has attracted some support, interestingly, from both sides of the debate: relativists who have embraced an objective constraint, and (more commonly) objectivists who have allowed some relativist dimensions. Here are some prominent examples of these mixed metaethical outlooks.

David Copp (1995) maintains that it is true that something is morally wrong only if it is wrong in relation to the justified moral code of some society, and a code is justified in a society only if the society would be rationally required to select it. Since which code it would be rationally required to select depends in part on the non-moral values of the society, and since these values differ from one society to another, something may be morally wrong for one society but not for another. Copp calls this position a form of moral relativism. However, he believes this relativism is significantly mitigated by the fact that which code a society is rationally required to select also depends on the basic needs of the society. Copp thinks all societies have the same basic needs. For example, every society has a need to maintain its population and system of cooperation from one generation to the next. Moreover, since meeting these basic needs is the most fundamental factor in determining the rationality of selecting a code, Copp thinks the content of all justified moral codes will tend to be quite similar. For instance, any such code will require that persons's basic needs for such things as physical survival, self-respect and friendship be promoted (these are said to be necessary for minimal rational agency). The theory is mixed insofar as the rationality of selecting a code depends partly on common features of human nature (basic needs) and partly on diverse features of different societies (values). Whether or not justified moral codes (and hence moral truths) would tend to be substantially similar, despite differences, as Copp argues, would depend on both the claim that all societies have the same basic needs and the claim that these needs are much more important than other values in determining which moral code it is rational for a society to select.

Wong (1996) defended a partly similar position, though one intended to allow for greater diversity in correct moral codes. He argued that more than one morality may be true, but there are limits on which moralities are true. The first point is a form of metaethical relativism: It says one morality may be true for one society and a conflicting morality may be true for another society. Hence, there is no one objectively correct morality for all societies. The second point, however, is a concession to moral objectivism. It acknowledges that objective factors concerning human nature and the human situation should determine whether or not, or to what extent, a given morality could be one of the true ones. The mere fact that a morality is accepted by a society does not guarantee that it has normative authority in that society. For example, given our biological and psychological make-up, not just anything could count as a good way of life. Again, given that most persons are somewhat self-interested and that society requires some measure of cooperation, any plausible morality will include a value of reciprocity (good in return for good on some proportional basis). Since these objective limitations are quite broad, they are insufficient in themselves to establish a specific and detailed morality: Many particular moralities are consistent with them, and the choice among these moralities must be determined by the cultures of different societies.

Wong has developed this approach at length in more recent work (2006). His “pluralistic relativism” continues to emphasize that there are universal constraints on what could be a true morality. The constraints are based on a naturalistic understanding of human nature and the circumstances of human life. For Wong, given a variety of human needs and the depth of self-interest, morality's function is to promote both social co-operation and individual flourishing. In addition, morality requires that persons have both effective agency and effective identity, and these can only be fostered in personal contexts such as the family. Hence, the impersonal perspective must be limited by the personal perspective. Any true morality would have to respect requirements such as these.

Nonetheless, according to Wong, the universal constraints are sufficiently open-ended that there is more than one way to respect them. Hence, there can be more than one true morality. This is pluralistic relativism. For Wong, the different true moralities need not be, and typically are not, completely different from one another. In fact, they often share some values (such as individual rights and social utility), but assign them different priorities.

Wong presents pluralistic relativism as the best explanation of what he calls “moral ambivalence,” the phenomenon of morally disagreeing with someone while recognizing that the person is still reasonable in making the conflicting judgment—to the point that one's confidence in being uniquely right is shaken. It might be wondered if moral ambivalence is sufficiently widespread to play a central role in determining whether or not moral relativism is correct. However, this should not detract attention from Wong's sustained and detailed argument that an empirically-based understanding of the nature and conditions of human life both limits and underdetermines what a true morality could be. In many respects, Wong's position is the most sophisticated form of relativism developed to date, and it has the resources to confront a number of the issues raised in the last section (for some critical responses to Wong, along with his replies, see Xiao and Huang 2014).

A somewhat similar mixed position has been advanced, though more tentatively, by Foot (2002a and 2002b; see also Scanlon 1995 and 1998: ch. 8). She argued that there are conceptual limitations on what could count as a moral code (as seen in section 4), and that there are common features of human nature that set limits on what a good life could be. For these reasons, there are some objective moral truths—for example, that the Nazi attempt to exterminate the Jews was morally wrong. However, Foot maintained, these considerations do not ensure that all moral disagreements can be rationally resolved. Hence, in some cases, a moral judgment may be true by reference to the standards of one society and false by reference to the standards of another society—but neither true nor false in any absolute sense (just as we might say with respect to standards of beauty).

Foot came to this mixed view from the direction of objectivism (in the form of a virtue theory), and it might be contended by some objectivists that she has conceded too much. Since there are objective criteria, what appear as rationally irresolvable disagreements might be resolvable through greater understanding of human nature. Or the objective criteria might establish that in some limited cases it is an objective moral truth that conflicting moral practices are both morally permissible. In view of such considerations, objectivists might argue, it is not necessary to have recourse to the otherwise problematic notion of relative moral truth.

A position related to Foot's has been advanced by Martha Nussbaum (1993). With explicit reference to Aristotle, she argued that there is one objectively correct understanding of the human good, and that this understanding provides a basis for criticizing the moral traditions of different societies. The specifics of this account are explained by a set of experiences or concerns, said to be common to all human beings and societies, such as fear, bodily appetite, distribution of resources, management of personal property, etc. Corresponding to each of these is a conception of living well, a virtue, namely the familiar Aristotelian virtues such as courage, moderation, justice, and generosity. Nussbaum acknowledged that there are disagreements about these virtues, and she raised an obvious relativist objection herself: Even if the experiences are universal, does human nature establish that there is one objectively correct way of living well with respect to each of these areas? In response, Nussbaum conceded that sometimes there may be more than one objectively correct conception of these virtues and that the specification of the conception may depend on the practices of a particular community.

As with Foot, Nussbaum came to this mixed position from the objectivist side of the debate. Some moral objectivists may think she has given up too much, and for a related reason many moral relativists may believe she has established rather little. For example, bodily appetites are indeed universal experiences, but there has been a wide range of responses to these—for example, across a spectrum from asceticism to hedonism. This appears to be one of the central areas of moral disagreement. In order to maintain her objectivist credentials, Nussbaum needs to show that human nature substantially constrains which of these responses could be morally appropriate. Some objectivists may say she has not shown this, but could, while relativists may doubt she could show it.

Mixed positions along the lines of those just discussed suppose that morality is objective in some respects, on account of some features of human nature, and relative in other respects. For the respects in which morality is relative, it is up to particular societies or individuals to determine which moral values to embrace. Hence, the authority of morality depends partly on objective factors and partly on the decisions of groups or individuals. Insofar as this is true, such mixed positions need to say something about the basis for these decisions and how conflicts are to be resolved (for example, when individuals dissent from groups or when people belong to different groups with conflicting values). The objective features of mixed positions may help resolve these issues, or may limit their import, but at the point where these features give out there remain some of the standard concerns about relativism (such as those raised in the last section).

Another approach might be construed as a mixed position, though it was not put forward in these terms. Isaiah Berlin (1998) argued that, though some moral values are universal, there are also many objective values that conflict and are not commensurable with one another. He called his position pluralism and rejected the label ‘relativism’ (see the entry on Isaiah Berlin). But if incommensurability implies that these conflicts cannot be rationally resolved, then it might suggest a concession to relativism.

Against such a position, an objectivist may ask why we should think objective goods are incommensurable: If X and Y are both objectively good, then why not say that the statement ‘X is better than Y’ (or a more restrictive comparative statement specifying respects or circumstances) is objectively true or false, even if this is difficult to know? Berlin's view was that there are many examples of conflicting goods—for example, justice and mercy, or liberty and equality—where it is implausible to suppose they are commensurable.

Finally, it should also be noted that a rather different kind of mixed position was proposed by Bernard Williams (1981 and 1985: ch. 9). He rejected what he called “strict relational relativism,” that ethical conceptions have validity only relative to a society. But he endorsed another form of relativism. This was explained by reference to a distinction between a “notional confrontation,” where a divergent outlook is known but not a real option for us, and a “real confrontation,” where a divergent outlook is a real option for us—something we might embrace without losing our grip on reality. Williams's “relativism of distance” says ethical appraisals are appropriate in real confrontations, but not in notional ones. For example, we could never embrace the outlook of a medieval samurai: Since this is a notional confrontation, it would be inappropriate to describe this outlook as just or unjust. This is the sense in which relativism is correct. But in real confrontations, relativism unhelpfully discourages the evaluation of another outlook that is a genuine option for us.

Williams was a strong critic of most forms of moral objectivism, yet he also criticized many of the nonobjectivist alternatives to objectivism. His outlook is not easily classified in terms of standard metaethical positions. With respect to his relativism of distance, it may be wondered why appraisals are inappropriate in notional confrontations: Why should the fact that an outlook is not a real option preclude us from thinking it is just or unjust? On the other hand, in real confrontations Williams thought the language of appraisal was appropriate, but he also thought these confrontations could involve rationally irresolvable disagreements. Though Williams rejects strict relational relativism, objectivists may argue that his position suffers from defects as serious as those that attend MMR. If the confrontations are real because the two outlooks have something in common, objectivists might ask, could this not provide a basis for resolving these disagreements?

The central theme in mixed positions is that neither relativism nor objectivism is wholly correct: At least in the terms in which they are often expressed, these alternatives are subject to serious objections, and yet they are motivated by genuine concerns. It might seem that a mixed position could be developed that would give us the best of both worlds (there are a number of other proposals along these lines; for example see Hampshire 1983 and 1989). However, an implication of most mixed positions (this does not apply to Williams) seems to be that, in some respect, some moral judgments are objectively true (or justified), while others have only relative truth (or justification). This should not be confused with the claim that an action may be right in some circumstances but not others. For example, a consequentialist view that polygamy is right in one society and wrong in another because it has good consequences in the first society and bad consequences in the second would not be a mixed position because the judgments “Polygamy is right in circumstances A” and “Polygamy is wrong in circumstances B” could both be true in an absolute sense. By contrast, a mixed position might say that “Polygamy is right” is true relative to one society and false relative to another (where the two societies differ, not necessarily in circumstances, but in fundamental values), while other moral judgments have absolute truth-value. This is a rather disunified conception of morality, and it invites many questions. A proponent of a mixed view would have to show that it is an accurate portrayal of our moral practices, or that it is a plausible proposal for reforming them.

8. Relativism and Tolerance
Relativism is sometimes associated with a normative position, usually pertaining to how people ought to regard or behave towards those with whom they morally disagree. The most prominent normative position in this connection concerns tolerance. In recent years, the idea that we should be tolerant has been increasingly accepted in some circles. At the same time, others have challenged this idea, and the philosophical understanding and justification of tolerance has become less obvious (see Heyd 1996 and the entry on toleration). The question here is whether moral relativism has something to contribute to these discussions, in particular, whether DMR or MMR provide support for tolerance (for discussion, see Graham 1996, Harrison 1976, Ivanhoe 2009, Kim and Wreen 2003, Prinz 2007: pp. 207-13 and Wong 1984: ch. 12). In this context, tolerance does not ordinarily mean indifference or absence of disapproval: It means having a policy of not interfering with the actions of persons that are based on moral judgments we reject, when the disagreement is not or cannot be rationally resolved. The context of discussion is often, but not always, moral disagreements between two societies. Does moral relativism provide support for tolerance in this sense?

Though many people seem to think it does, philosophers generally think they are mistaken. DMR may provide the occasion for tolerance, but it could not imply that tolerance is morally obligatory or even permissible. DMR simply tells us there are moral disagreements. Recognition of this fact, by itself, entails nothing about how we should act towards those with whom we disagree. MMR fares no better. For one thing, MMR cannot very well imply that it is an objective moral truth that we should be tolerant: MMR denies that there are such truths. (A mixed position could contend that tolerance is the only objective moral truth, all others being relative; but it would have to be shown that this is more than an ad hoc maneuver.) It might be said that MMR implies that tolerance is a relative truth. However, even this is problematic. According to MMR, understood to concern truth, the truth-value of statements may vary from society to society. Hence, the statement, “people ought to be tolerant” , may be true in some societies and false in others. MMR by itself does not entail that T is true in any society, and may in fact have the result that T is false in some societies (a similar point may be made with respect to justification).

Some objectivists may add that in some cases we should be tolerant of those with whom we morally disagree, but that only objectivists can establish this as an objective moral truth (for example, by drawing on arguments in the liberal tradition from Locke or Mill). To the objection that moral objectivism implies intolerance (or imperialism), objectivists typically contend that the fact that we regard a society as morally wrong in some respect does not entail that we should interfere with it.

Nonetheless, the thought persists among some relativists that there is a philosophically significant connection between relativism and tolerance. Perhaps the conjunction of MMR and an ethical principle could give us a reason for tolerance we would not have on the basis of the ethical principle alone. Such an approach has been proposed by Wong (1984: ch. 12). The principle is, roughly speaking, that we should not interfere with people unless we could justify this interference to them (if they were rational and well-informed in relevant respects). Wong called this “the justification principle.” Of course, it is already a tolerance principle of sorts. The idea is that it gains broader scope if MMR is correct. Let us suppose the statement that there is an individual right to freedom of speech is true and justified for our society, but is false and unjustified in another society in which the press is restricted for the good of the community. In this case, given MMR, our society might not be able to justify interference to the restrictive society concerning freedom of the press. Any justification we could give would appeal to values that are authoritative for us, not them, and no appeal to logic or facts alone would give them a reason to accept our justification.

If the justification principle were widely accepted, this argument might explain why some people have had good reason to think there is a connection between relativism and tolerance. But there is a question about whether the position is stable. Wong derived the justification principle from Kant, and Kant rejected MMR. If we were to accept MMR, would we still have reason to accept the justification principle? Wong thought we might, perhaps on the basis of considerations quite independent of Kant. In any case, this argument would only show that MMR plays a role in an argument for tolerance that is relevant to people in a society that accepted the justification principle. The argument does not establish that there is a general connection between relativism and tolerance. Nor does it undermine the contention that MMR may have the result that T is true in some societies and false in others.

In his more recent defense of pluralistic relativism (2006), Wong has argued that, since some serious moral disagreements are inevitable, any adequate morality will include the value of what he calls accommodation. This involves a commitment to peaceful and non-coercive relationships with persons with whom we disagree. Accommodation appears to be related to tolerance, but Wong argues for more than this: we should also try to learn from others, compromise with them, preserve relationships with them, etc. Wong's defense of accommodation is immune to the objection that relativism cannot be a basis for such a universal value because his defense purports to be based on considerations that any adequate morality should recognize. However, for this reason, though it presupposes the considerations supporting the relativist dimension of his position (there is no single true morality), it argues from the non-relativist dimension (there are universal constraints any morality should accept, in particular, that one function of morality is to promote social co-operation). Hence, it is not strictly speaking an argument from relativism to accommodation.

As was noted in section 3, aside from the philosophical question whether or not some form of moral relativism provides a reason for attitudes such as tolerance, there is the psychological question whether or not people who accept relativism are more likely to be tolerant. As was seen, there is some evidence that relativists are more tolerant than objectivists, and it has been claimed that, even if relativism does not justify tolerance, it would be a positive feature of relativism that acceptance of it makes people more tolerant (see Prinz 2007: 208). Of course, this judgment presupposes that, in some sense, it is good to be tolerant.

Bibliography

American Anthropological Association Executive Board, 1947, “Statement on Human Rights,” American Anthropologist, 49: 539–43.
Appiah, K. A., 2006, Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers, New York: W.W. Norton.
Audi, R., 2007, Moral Value and Human Diversity, New York: Oxford University Press.
Baghramian, M., 2004, Relativism, London: Routledge.
Beebe, J.R., 2010, “Moral Relativism in Context,” Nous, 44: 691–724.
–––, 2014, “How Different Kinds of Disagreement Impact Folk Metaethical Judgments,” in H. Sarkissian and J.C. Wright (eds.) Advances in Experimental Moral Psychology, London: Bloomsbury, 167–87.
Benbaji, Y. and M. Fisch, 2004, “Through Thick and Thin: A New Defense of Cultural Relativism,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 42: 1–24.
Benedict, R, 1934, Patterns of Culture, Boston MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Berlin, I., 1998, “The Pursuit of the Ideal,” in Berlin, The Proper Study of Mankind: An Anthology of Essays, H. Hardy and R. Hausheer (eds.), New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux. 1–16. Original Publication Date: 1988.
Bjornsson, G. and S. Finlay, 2010, “Metaethical Contextualism Defended,” Ethics, 121: 7–36.
Blackburn, S., 1984, Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
–––, 1998, Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
–––, 1999, “Is Objective Moral Justification Possible on a Quasi-realist Foundation?,” Inquiry, 42: 213–28.
Bloomfield, P., 2003, “Is There a Moral High Ground?,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 41: 511–26.
Boghossian, P., 2006, Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
–––, 2011a,“Three Kinds of Relativism,” in S.D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 53–69.
–––, 2011b, “The Maze of Moral Relativism,” The New York Times, July 24 (Opinion pages, Opinionator, The Stone).
Bok, S., 1995, Common Values, Columbia MO: University of Missouri Press.
Brady, M., 2010, “Disappointment,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 84: 179–98.
Brandt, R.B., 1954, Hopi Ethics: A Theoretical Analysis, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
–––, 1984, “Relativism Refuted?,” The Monist, 67: 297–307.
Brogaard, B., 2008, “Moral Contextualism and Moral Relativism,” Philosophical Quarterly, 58: 385–409.
–––, 2012, “Moral Relativism and Moral Expressivism,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50: 538–56.
Capps, D., M.P. Lynch and D. Massey, 2008, “A Coherent Moral Relativism,” Synthese, 151: 1–26.
Chuang-Tzu, 2001, The Inner Chapters, edited and translated by A.C. Graham, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. Original Publication Date: 1981.
Code, L., 1995, “Must a Feminist Be a Relativist After All?,” in Code, Rhetorical Spaces: Essays on Gendered Locations, New York: Routledge, 185–207.
Coliva, A. and S. Moruzzi, 2012, “Truth Relativists Can't Trump Moral Progress,” Analytic Philosophy, 53: 48–57.
Cook, J.W., 1999, Morality and Cultural Differences, New York: Oxford University Press.
Cooper, D., 1978, “Moral Relativism,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 3: 97–108.
Copp, D., 1995, Morality, Normativity, and Society, New York: Oxford University Press.
Corradetti, C., 2009, Relativism and Human Rights: A Theory of Pluralistic Universalism, Dordrecht: Springer.
Davidson, D., 1984, “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme” in Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 183–98. Original Publication Date: 1973–74.
–––, 2004a, “Expressing Evaluations” in Davidson, Problems of Rationality, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 19–37. Original Publication Date: 1984.
–––, 2004b, “The Objectivity of Values” in Davidson, Problems of Rationality, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 39–57. Original Publication Date: 1995.
Donnelly, J., 1984, “Cultural Relativism and Universal Human Rights,” Human Rights Quarterly, 6: 400–419.
–––, 2013, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, Third Edition, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Doris, J.M. and A. Plakias, 2008, “How to Argue about Disagreement: Evaluative Diversity and Moral Realism,” in W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.) Moral Psychology, Volume 2: The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity, Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 303–31.
Dreier, J., 1990, “Internalism and Speaker Relativism,” Ethics, 101: 6–26.
–––, 2006, “Moral Relativism and Moral Nihilism,” in D. Copp (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, New York: Oxford University Press, 240–64.
Duncker, K., 1939, “Ethical Relativity?”, Mind 48: 39–57.
Egan, A., 2012, “Relativist Dispositional Theories of Value,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50: 557–82.
Elgin, C. Z., 1989, “The Relativity of Fact and the Objectivity of Value,” in M. Krausz (ed.) Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 86–98.
Feltz, A. and E.T. Cokely, 2008, “The Fragmented Folk: More Evidence of Stable Individual Differences in Moral Judgments and Folk Intuitions,” in B.C. Love, K. McRae and V.M. Sloutsky (eds.) Proceedings of the 30th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society, 1771–76.
Fleischacker, S., 1992, Integrity and Moral Relativism, Leiden: E.J. Brill.
Foot, P., 1978a, “Moral Arguments,” in Foot, Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 96–109, Original Publication Date: 1958.
–––, 1978b, “Moral Beliefs,” in Foot, Virtues and Vices and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 110–31, Original Publication Date: 1958–59.
–––, 2002a, “Morality and Art,” in Foot, Moral Dilemmas and Other Topics in Moral Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 5–19, Original Publication Date: 1972.
–––, 2002b, “Moral Relativism,” in Foot, Moral Dilemmas and Other Topics in Moral Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 20–36, Original Publication Date: 1979.
Fricker, M., 2010, “The Relativism of Blame and Williams's Relativism of Distance,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 84: 151–77.
Garcia, J.L.A., 1988, “Relativism and Moral Divergence,” Metaphilosophy, 19: 264–81.
Geertz, C., 2000, Available Light: Anthropological Reflections on Philosophical Topics, Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.
Gewirth, A., 1994, “Is Cultural Pluralism Relevant to Moral Knowledge?,” in E.F. Paul, F.D. Miller, Jr., and J. Paul (eds.) Cultural Pluralism and Moral Knowledge, Cambridge U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 22–43.
Gill, M.B., 2008, “Metaethical Variability, Incoherence, and Error,” in W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.) Moral Psychology, Volume 2: The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity, Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 387–401.
Goodwin, G.P. and J.M. Darley, 2008, “The Psychology of Meta-ethics: Exploring Objectivism,” Cognition, 106: 1339–66.
–––, 2010, “The Perceived Objectivity of Ethical Beliefs: Psychological Findings and Implications for Public Policy,” Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1: 161-88.
Gowans, C., (ed.), 2000, Moral Disagreements: Classic and Contemporary Readings, London: Routledge.
–––, 2004, “A Priori Refutations of Disagreement Arguments against Moral Objectivity: Why Experience Matters,” Journal of Value Inquiry, 38: 141–57.
–––, 2011,“Virtue Ethics and Moral Relativism,” in S.D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 391–410.
Graham, G., 1996, “Tolerance, Pluralism, and Relativism,” in D. Heyd (ed.) Toleration: An Elusive Virtue, Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 44–59.
Hales, S., 2009, “Moral Relativism and Evolutionary Psychology,” Synthese, 166: 431-47.
–––, (ed.), 2011, A Companion to Relativism, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
Hampshire, S., 1983, “Morality and Conflict,” in Hampshire, Morality and Conflict, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 140–169.
–––, 1989, Innocence and Experience, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
Hare, R.M., 1981, Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and Point, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Harman, G., 1996, “Moral Relativism,” in G. Harman and J.J. Thompson (eds.) Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity, Cambridge MA: Blackwell Publishers, 3–64.
–––, 2000a, “Moral Relativism Defended,” in Harman, Explaining Value: And Other Essays in Moral Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 3–19. Original Publication Date: 1975.
–––, 2000b, “Is There a Single True Morality?,” in Harman, Explaining Value: And Other Essays in Moral Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 77–99. Original Publication Date: 1984.
–––, 2015, “Moral Relativism is Moral Realism,” Philosophical Studies, 172: 855–63.
Harrison, G., 1976, “Relativism and Tolerance,” Ethics, 86: 122–35.
Hatch, E., 1983, Culture and Morality: The Relativity of Values in Anthropology, New York: Columbia University Press.
Herskovits, M.J., 1972, Cultural Relativism: Perspectives in Cultural Pluralism, F. Herskovits (ed.), New York: Random House.
Heyd, D., (ed.), 1996, Toleration: An Elusive Virtue, Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hills, A, 2013, “Faultless Moral Disagreement,” Ratio, 26: 410–27.
Horgan, T. and M. Timmons, 2006, “Expressivism, Yes! Relativism, No!,” in R. Shafer-Landau (ed.) Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 73–98.
Ivanhoe, P.J., 2009, “Pluralism, Toleration, and Ethical Promiscuity,” Journal of Religious Ethics, 37: 311–29.
Jackson, F., 1998, From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defense of Conceptual Analysis, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kellenberger, J., 2001, Moral Relativism, Moral Diversity, and Human Relationships, University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.
–––, 2008, Moral Relativism: A Dialogue. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers.
Kim, H-K. and M. Wreen, 2003, “Relativism, Absolutism, and Tolerance,” Metaphilosophy, 34: 447–59.
Kirchin, S., 2000, “Quasi-Realism, Sensibility Theory, and Ethical Relativism,” Inquiry, 43: 413–28.
Kölbel, M., 2004, “Faultless Disagreement,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104: 53–73.
–––, 2005, “Moral Relativism,” in T. Tännsjö and D. Westerstahl (eds.) Lectures on Relativism, Philosophical Communications, Red Series No. 40, Göteburg University, 51–72.
Krausz, M., (ed.), 1989, Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation, Notre Dame IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
––– (ed.), 2010, Relativism: A Contemporary Anthology, New York: Columbia University Press.
–––, 2011, “Varieties of Relativism and the Reach of Reasons,” in S.D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 70–84.
Krausz, M. and J.W. Meiland, (eds.), 1982, Relativism: Cognitive and Moral, Notre Dame IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Küng, H., (ed.), 1996, Yes to a Global Ethic: Voices from Religion and Politics, New York: Continuum.
Ladd, J., 1957, The Structure of a Moral Code: A Philosophical Analysis of Ethical Discourse Applied to the Ethics of the Navaho Indians, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
––– (ed.), 1985, Ethical Relativism. Lanham MD: University Press of America.
Levy, N., 2002, Moral Relativism: A Short Introduction, Oxford: Oneworld Publications.
––– 2003, “Descriptive Relativism: Assessing the Evidence,” The Journal of Value Inquiry, 37: 165–77.
Lillehammer, H., 2007, “Davidson on Value and Objectivity,” Dialectica, 61: 203–17.
Lķpez de Sa, 2011,“The Many Relativisms: Index, Context, and Beyond,” in S.D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 102–17.
Lukes, S., 2008, Moral Relativism, New York: Picador.
Lyons, D., 1976, “Ethical Relativism and the Problem of Incoherence,” Ethics, 86: 107–21
MacIntyre, A., 1988, Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, Notre Dame IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
–––, 1994, “Moral Relativism, Truth and Justification,” in L. Gormally (ed.) Moral Truth and Moral Tradition: Essays in Honour of Peter Geach and Elizabeth Anscombe, Blackrock, County Dublin: Four Courts Press, 6–24.
Macklin, R., 1999, Against Relativism: Cultural Diversity and the Search for Ethical Universals in Medicine, New York: Oxford University Press.
Mead, M., 1928, Coming of Age in Samoa, New York: William Morrow.
Miller, C.B., 2002, “Rorty and Moral Relativism,” European Journal of Philosophy, 10: 354–74.
–––, 2011, “Moral Relativism and Moral Psychology,” in S.D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 346–67.
Moody-Adams, M.M., 1997, Fieldwork in Familiar Places: Morality, Culture, and Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Moser, P.K. and T.L. Carson, (eds.), 2001, Moral Relativism: A Reader, New York: Oxford University Press.
Myers, R.H., 2004, “Finding Value in Davidson,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 34: 107–36.
Nichols, S., 2004, “After Objectivity: An Empirical Study of Moral Judgment,” Philosophical Psychology, 17: 3–26.
Nussbaum, M.C., 1993, “Non-relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach” in M. Nussbaum and A. Sen (eds.) The Quality of Life, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 242–69.
–––, 1999, “Judging Other Cultures: The Case of Genital Mutilation,” in Nussbaum, Sex and Social Justice, New York: Oxford University Press, 118–29.
Okin, S.M., 1998, “Feminism, Women's Human Rights, and Cultural Differences,” Hypatia, 13: 32–52.
Olinder, R.F., 2012, “Moral and Metaethical Pluralism: Unity in Variation,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50: 583–601.
–––, 2013, “Moral Relativism, Error Theory, and Ascriptions of Mistakes,” The Journal of Philosophy, 110: 564-80.
Paul, E.F., F.D. Miller and J. Paul (eds.), 2008, Objectivism, Subjectivism, and Relativism in Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Prinz, J.J., 2007, The Emotional Construction of Morals, New York: Oxford University Press.
–––, 2009, “The Significance of Moral Variation: Replies to Tiberius, Gert and Doris,” Analysis Reviews, 69: 731-45.
Quintelier, K.J.P. and M.T. Fessler, 2012, “Varying Versions of Moral Relativism: The Philosophy and Psychology of Normative Relativism,” Biology and Philosophy, 27: 95-113.
Rachels, J., 1999, “The Challenge of Cultural Relativism,” The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 3rd ed., New York: Random House, 20–36.
Raz, J., 2003, The Practice of Value, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Renteln, A.D., 1985, “The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights,” Human Rights Quarterly, 7: 514–40.
Rescher, N., 2008, “Moral Objectivity,” in E.F. Paul, F.D. Miller, Jr., and J. Paul (eds.) Objectivism, Subjectivism, and Relativism in Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 393-409.
Rorty, R., 1991, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.
Rovane, C., 2002, “Earning the Right to Realism or Relativism in Ethics,” Nous, 36 (Supplement): 264–85.
–––, 2011, “Relativism Requires Alternatives, Not Disagreement or Relative Truth,” in S.D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 31–52.
–––, 2013, The Metaphysics and Ethics of Relativism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Ryan, J.A., 2003, “Moral Relativism and the Argument from Disagreement,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 34: 377–86.
Sarkissian, H., forthcoming, “Aspects of Folk Morality: Objectivism and Relativism,” in W. Buckwalter and J. Sytsma (eds.) A Companion to Experimental Philosophy, London: Blackwell.
Sarkissian, H., J. Park, D. Tien, J. C. Wright, and J. Knobe, 2011, “Folk Moral Relativism,” Mind & Language, 26: 482-505.
Scanlon, T.M., 1995, “Fear of Relativism,” in R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence, and W. Quinn (eds.) Virtues and Reasons: Philippa Foot and Moral Theory, Oxford: Clarendon Press. 219–46.
–––, 1998, What We Owe to Each Other, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
Schafer, K, 2012, “Assessor Relativism and the Problem of Moral Disagreement,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50: 602–20.
Shafer-Landau, R., 2003, Moral Realism: A Defense, New York: Oxford University Press.
–––, 2009, “A Defense of Categorical Reasons,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 109 (2): 189-206.
Shweder, R.A., 1991, Thinking Through Cultures: Expeditions in Cultural Psychology. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
Sinnott-Armstrong, W., 2009, “Mixed-up Meta-ethics,” Philosophical Issues, 19: 235–56.
Smith, M., 1991, “Realism,” in P. Singer (ed.) A Companion to Ethics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. 399–410.
Snare, F., 1980, “The Diversity of Morals,” Mind, 89: 353–69.
–––, 1992, The Nature of Moral Thinking, London: Routledge.
Sreenivasan, G., 2001, “Understanding Alien Morals,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62: 1–32.
Stout, J., 1988, Ethics After Babel: The Languages of Morals and Their Discontents, Boston: Beacon Press.
Streiffer, R., 2003, Moral Relativism and Reasons for Action, New York: Routledge.
Sturgeon, N.L., 1994, “Moral Disagreement and Moral Relativism,” in E.F. Paul, F.D. Miller, Jr., and J. Paul (eds.) Cultural Pluralism and Moral Knowledge, Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press. 80–115.
Sumner, W.G., 1906, Folkways, Boston: Ginn and Company.
Tasioulas, J., 1998, “Relativism, Realism, and Reflection,” Inquiry, 41: 377–410.
Tersman, F., 2006, Moral Disagreement, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tännsjö, T., 2007, “Moral Relativism,” Philosophical Studies, 135: 123–43.
Tiberius, V., 2009, “The Practical Irrelevance of Relativism,” Analysis Reviews, 69: 722–31.
Velleman, J.D., 2013, Foundations for Moral Relativism, Cambridge, UK: Open Book Publishers.
Walzer, M., 1994, Thick and Thin: Moral Argument at Home and Abroad, Notre Dame IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Wattles, J., 1996, The Golden Rule, New York: Oxford University Press.
Wellman, C., 1963, “The Ethical Implications of Cultural Relativity,” The Journal of Philosophy, 60: 169–84.
–––, 1975, “Ethical Disagreement and Objective Truth,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 12: 211–21.
Westermarck, Edward, 1906–8, The Origin and Development of the Moral Ideas, 2 volumes, New York: The Macmillan Company.
–––, 1932, Ethical Relativity, New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Wiggins, D., 1990-91, “Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 91: 61–85.
Williams, B., 1972, Morality: An Introduction to Ethics, New York: Harper & Row.
–––, 1981, “The Truth in Relativism,” in Williams, Moral Luck, Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press, 132–43. Original Publication Date: 1974–75.
–––, 1985, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
Wong, D.B., 1984, Moral Relativity, Berkeley CA: University of California Press.
–––, 1986, “On Moral Realism without Foundations,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 24 (Supplement): 95–113.
––– ,1996, “Pluralistic Relativism,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Moral Concepts, 20: 378–399.
–––, 2006, Natural Moralities: A Defense of Pluralistic Relativism, New York: Oxford University Press.
–––, 2011,“Relativist Explanation of Interpersonal and Group Disagreement,” in S.D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 411–29.
Wright, C., 2008, “Fear of Relativism?,” Philosophical Studies, 141: 379–90.
Wright, J.C., J. Cullum and N. Schwab, 2008, “The Cognitive and Affective Dimensions of Moral Conviction: Implications for Attitudinal and Behavioral Measures of Interpersonal Tolerance,” Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34: 1461–76.
Wright, J.C., P.T. Grandjean and C.B. McWhite, 2013, “The Meta-ethical Grounding of our Moral Beliefs: Evidence for Meta-ethical Pluralism,” Philosophical Psychology, 26: 336–61.
Wright, J. C., C.B. McWhite and P.T. Grandjean, 2014, “The Cognitive Mechanisms of Intolerance: Do Our Meta-Ethical Commitments Matter,” in T. Lombrozo, J. Knobe and S. Nichols (eds.) Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, Vol. 1, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 28–61.
Xiao, Y. and Y. Huang, (eds.), 2014, Moral Relativism and Chinese Philosophy: David Wong and his Critics, Albany, NY: SUNY Press.






 
Reply With Quote